sciencepolice2010 launches

The basis of science is as important as science itself.  Our subconscious minds (and genomes) are designed to try to operate the principles of science; we handicap ourselves by not using those principles consciously.

Every scientist thinks they are the world expert on the nature and usage of science – yet they don’t always appreciate their most valuable and basic understandings come from the philosophy of science, which they’ve usually picked up haphazardly from others.

Everyone has a philosophy whether they accept it or not; likewise every scientist has a philosophy of science.  It’s the basic rules of their thinking.

Many philosophers of science are themselves pretty good scientists, yet most other scientists think or even say that philosophers of science are timewasting idiots.  Philosophy of science is not separate from sciences but occupies the common principles across the highest levels of all of them, and allows useful transference between them.

Because they can do their basic job well, scientists often feel they know everything relating to science.  But of course, all too often they don’t know what they don’t know – but are too complacent to try to find out.

Getting science wrong matters, as it allows huge and costly fiascos like the disputed dangers of smoking, disputed global climate change, and vaccination disputes.  These could be minimised if scientists bit two bullets:

1:  Learn the full but trivial principles of science properly themselves;

2:  Put them across to the world.

To avoid the challenge of relating every piece of science directly to the whole cloud of philosophy of science, the rules here take up an intermediate position. Relating them to the whole of philosophy of science is one thing; relating science to them is separate… and those two separate tasks are less of a challenge than the whole task in one lump. Since the rules are intermediate between philosophy of science which converges to them from above, and pieces of science which converge to them from below, the rules can be symbolised by the form of the Cyrillic character Ж (pronounced zhe as in the French ‘je’).

Rules are good now because the character of philosophy has inevitably encouraged indecision. This in turn has allowed pseudoscientific thinking to run wild and free all over the place. The rules do not arise from publishing issues, or from academic social powerplay, but are designed with guidance in scientific thought for individuals in mind. This includes individual robots, since Ж is meant to be usable as a system specification for designing scientific thought in robots, and was written with this requirement in mind.

This blog will incidentally explain the reasons for some of the principles but those explanations have been traditionally and studiously ignored for so long that often just the principles will be presented, and from to time to time, the results of the folly of ignoring them will be demonstrated.

The single page pdf can be downloaded from here on condition that it is printed off and widely distributed in electronic or any other form (unmodified of course):

…Or read the principles in this posting:

Ж – Sciencepolice-14.

1) Science is the generation, judging and honing of theories which model (i.e. explain or predict) the best. Only this counts so distinctions between theory, hypothesis, conjecture etc. are artificial.

2) The worth of a theory depends on such aspects as accuracy, generality, simplicity, and the degree to which its implications are genuine predictions (and the more surprising the better).

3) Theories can be rejected individually for not explaining evidence, or judged against each other.

4) An attempt to refute a theory does not require a replacement to be offered. Science isn’t politics.

5) It can be good science merely to “rough out” a theory or a class of theories for consideration.

6) A theory is refuted only when all its reasonable instantiations are refuted, not just one. Fixing faults in a theory can mar its other qualities, yet repair is still basic to knowledge development.

7) Extraordinary claims do not require extraordinary evidence and might need no new evidence: to require it would assume theorists in the field have been perfect; it’s perfectly possible people just haven’t thought of the new theory before. Theories do not spring automatically from observations.

8) New theories can violate and replace the old if the whole knowledge base’s modelling improves. Theories must swim amongst others at various levels, but it’s no good saying “It gets so complex it’s impossible”. Popper-based knowledge engineering works, even with complex uncertainties, but it’s guidelines, not pure mathematics. It underlies scientific experimentation and supports natural and artificial minds. Wet-ware has survived by aping it, always roughly, for over a billion years.

9) There are no absolute facts, proofs or truths; outside mathematics at least, they are convenient untruths that can simplify our thinking. Proof needs to demonstrate the impossibility of any competing theory, known or not, of equivalent or superior power, whereas disproof merely requires the presentation of evidence inconsistent with the one theory. Knowledge is beliefs, not facts.

10) Evidence is those observations not well explained by a theory, or not as well explained by one theory as by another. Positive but non-comparative evidence (explained by a theory), though useful in the black art of generation, merely progresses testing. ‘Positive evidence’ must not be trumpeted as ‘evidence for’ a theory when competing theories also explain it. Papers and journals should ensure the full landscape and pattern of posable theories are reasonably accounted for.

11) An untestable theory is one which is intrinsically logically untestable, not one for which no technique for testing it is yet known to some person, or indeed anyone. Deducing the scope of implications, effects, or influences of a hypothesis (via which it might be tested) can be slow and unending. ‘Untestable’ is a rare category, not to be routinely flung at everyone else’s new theory.

12) Tests a new theory can uniquely pass are best offered, and may be needed for superiority, but not for pseudo-criteria like theory status, false ‘testability’, or truth. Insisting on a mechanism for a theory is a classic error. A theory often inspires the discovery of its mechanisms and special tests.

13) Strictures apply to judging theories but not to generating them. Judging a theory by the ‘worth’ or number of its supporters is unscientific: good ideas too often start with a single supporter of little renown. Far from being essential scientific principles, the only value of ‘peer review’ and ‘consensus’ is the extent, if any, to which they aid implementation of the genuine principles; their habit of repressing good new theories needs conscious and constant forfending.

14) Historical disciplines (e.g. palaeontology and archaeology) often test by future discovery, not experiment. In such disciplines, evidence and demonstration may be probabilistic or qualitative, and rely on complex variously valid world models left in individual minds by diverse experiences. Typically, historical sciences theorise past events given present evidence (abduction). Inductive sciences invent laws, or describe/model structures or processes; ‘applied sciences’ deduce futures or achieve goals. Despite differences, many principles apply to all sciences, though the importance of repeatability for inductive sciences does not make it a basic principle of historical disciplines.

This entry was posted in Essential First Post, Philosophy of science. Bookmark the permalink.

2 Responses to sciencepolice2010 launches

  1. Pingback: Ornithoscelida. Note to Matt Baron on Baron et al. | sciencepolice2010

  2. Pingback: Even the Good Guys: Extraordinary claims require extraordinary evidence. Really? | sciencepolice2010

Leave a comment

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.